SOPHIE BOTROS - PUBLICATIONS - RESPONSE


Home Page
Publications
Conferences / Working Parties
Abstracts

Response to Neil Sinclair's review of my book Hume, Reason and Morality: A Legacy of Contradiction? in Mind Vol.116, July 2007

                The first question takes off from   the  ‘practicality’  argument formulated by  Hume in  Treatise 3.1.1, and the troublesome ambiguities  surrounding its second premise.  I proposed that, in order to resolve them,  we  should  take  Hume, when he  stresses the utter motivational impotence of reason, to  have in mind  the moral rationalists’ notion .   Sinclair agrees (734)  that  Hume both  “has rationalist opponents in mind in 3.1.1” and  “objects to their  view that ‘eternal fitnesses’ can influence the will (3.1.1:23)”.  But he rejects that  proposal on grounds that   “at no point  in this discussion does Hume even hint at using ‘reason’ to refer to [their] fitnesses”.   The proposal is not to the effect that  Hume explicitly announced such a use of  ‘reason’ -  nothing so deliberate or systematic  on Hume‘s part.  But, quite independently  of the proposal’s merits,   the implication of  Sinclair’s claim, that Hume never did  on any occasion use ‘reason’ to refer to the rationalists’  notion, and that we are never entitled to substitute ‘reason’  for  ‘fitnesses’,  is contentious.  

                Given  that  the  rationalists are   the main target of  3.1.1,  it would be astonishing  if Hume never   used ‘reason’  in this section to refer to their concept.  Indeed we need only look as far as  paragraph 4  to find an example.  Here  Hume expounds their position in terms of   (Clarke‘s) “ eternal fitnesses and unfitnesses of things”  and (Cudworth’s) “ immutable measures of right and wrong”.  But he prefaces his exposition  by making the general point that    “according to [all these systems] virtue is nothing but a conformity with reason”.  What else could ‘reason’ refer to here but his rationalist opponents’  concept?1

                 Sinclair will perhaps point out that   he  does not claim, or imply,  that Hume never uses ‘reason’ to refer to his rationalists’ opponents’ reason, but rather that he never uses it  to refer to their ‘fitnesses and unfitnesses’.   But this would suggest that Hume drew a sharp distinction between the moral rationalists’ concept of reason, or rationality, and  their concept of  ‘fitnesses and unfitnesses’.   But this is not true.     Hume is quite explicit  that (Clarke’s)  “eternal immutable fitnesses and unfitnesses of things” and (Cudworth’s) “eternal measures of good and evil”, though they are  relations existing outside us, are rational .  Thus  he  does not content himself with saying  (para.4)  that these “eternal measures” are the same to “every rational being that considers them”, which would  be consistent with reason as merely a mental activity of ours.    He speaks of them (para.23) as themselves   “ eternal rational measures of right and wrong” (my italics).   In this way, as any great philosopher should,  he does justice to Clarke’s and Cudworth’s repeated identification of  ‘reason’ with ‘the reason of things’2 or ‘the reason of the world’3 , at the same time as utterly repudiating their view.

                 Sinclair might now suggest that  his own  phrase  “in this discussion”    refers only to  paragraph 23 which he cites as the source of  his quotation.   Actually  Hume neither refers to  ‘eternal fitnesses’ nor  denies their influence  on  the will in that paragraph.   But even if  we  concentrate on paragraph 22, where he does say these things, it is unclear how this could help.  We have seen, first, that   it is unwise, if not impossible, to try to prize apart   the rationalists’ notion of reason from their notion of  ‘the  fitnesses and unfitnesses of things’,  since for them ‘reason’  is essentially  ‘the reason of the world’  or  ‘the reason of things’.  Secondly, there is  no  evidence that Hume was ever so foolish as to make this mistake.   We are therefore entitled to  take his rejection  of their view  that these  ‘eternal fitnesses’ could  influence the will as also a rejection of their view that  reason could do so.   But it is then hard  to maintain that he would have  regarded his famous  descriptive phrase  “perfectly inert” as inapplicable  to the rationalists’ notion of reason.  On the contrary, it must have seemed, from his  point of view,   highly applicable.   The rationalists cannot, he might have said, posit such an inert concept of reason as the basis of anything so active as morality.    We should not of course immediately jump to the conclusion that  when Hume  described reason as “perfectly inert” (3.1.1:8),  the rationalist concept was, or even may  have been, implicated.  That  demands  much more argument which I will not repeat here.  

                 The second  question of interpretation  relates to   the ‘direction of fit’ account of desire and belief.   Sinclair does not agree that   this account   presupposes that  ‘it is a good thing for there to be a fit between desire and the world…..in every instance of desire ’.  He comments (734): “It would certainly be a surprise to defenders of the direction-of-fit account that it implied such evaluative claims”.   But these “evaluative claims”  are  merely paraphrases, or ways of drawing out the implications   (since otherwise they are intolerably obscure) of  Humberstone’s remark, in his classic discussion4  that, when there is this fit  “We have a sense of things going right”, and   Zangwill’s remark5 that  when there isn’t this fit, “That’s a fault in the world”.     It is a real question whether the ‘direction of fit’ account can be given without substantive use of evaluative language. 

 

                                                                                NOTES                 

                                                                               

1. Nor is this the first time Hume has used “reason” in a sense which he  proposes to repudiate.  To cite just one other example, at  2.3.3:1,   he speaks of those systems of morality of which the chief distinguishing feature is   “the supposed pre-eminence of reason over passion” ,  and  goes on that in these systems   “The eternity, invariableness and divine origin of the former have been displayed to the best advantage”.    Clearly  “the former”   refers to  “reason”.   

2. Clarke, Samuel (1728) A Discourse of Natural Religion, selections reprinted in D.D. Raphael (ed.) (1969) British Moralists 1650-1800, I: Hobbes-Gay: 231.

3.Cudworth, Ralph (1731) A Treatise Concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality, reprinted in Raphael, ibid: 134.

4.Humberstone, L.(1992) “Direction of fit”, Mind 101:72

5.Zangwill, N.(1996) “Direction of fit and normative functionalism” Philosophical Studies 91:177.

 

 

SOPHIE BOTROS,  Institute of Philosophy, School of Advanced Studies, London University.